Oct 25th 2013 GMT
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Matthias Unterhuber (2013). Possible Worlds Semantics
for Indicative and Counterfactual Conditionals? A Formal Philosophical Inquiry
Into Chellas-Segerberg Semantics. Ontos.
Conditional structures lie at the heart of the sciences,
humanities, and everyday reasoning. It is hence not surprising that conditional
logics – logics specifically designed to account for natural language
conditionals – are an active and interdisciplinary area. The present book gives
a formal and a philosophical account of indicative and counterfactual conditionals
in terms of Chellas-Segerberg semantics. For that purpose a range of topics are
discussed such as Bennett’s arguments against truth value based semantics for
indicative conditionals.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Mehmet
Karabela (2013). Ibn
Al-Rawandi. In Ibrahim Kalin (ed.), The Oxford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, Science, and Technology in Islam. Oxford University Press.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Rob Lovering has recently argued that God is not omniscient on
the grounds that (1) in order to be omniscient a subject must not only know all
truths always but also know what it's like not to know a truth, and (2) God
cannot fulfil both of these requirements. I show that Lovering's argument is
unsuccessful since he inadequately supports (1) and (2), and since there are
several serious doubts about (2). I also show that Lovering does not otherwise
indicate that God is not maximally great.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Alejandra Mancilla (2013). Det Vi Eide Førfast
Eiendom. Hugo Grotius Og Suum (What We Own Before Property: Hugo Grotius and
the Suum). Arr, Idéhistorisk Tiddskrift 3:3-14.
At the basis of modern natural law theories, the concept of the
suum, or what belongs to the person (in Latin, his, her, its, their own), has
received little scholarly attention despite its importance both in explaining
and justifying not only the genealogy of property, but also that of morality
and war.1 In this paper I examine Hugo Grotius's what it is, what things it
includes, what rights it gives rise to and how it is extended in the transition
from the state of nature to civil society. I then briefly point out how
bringing this concept back to the fore could help to illuminate the current
discussion on the foundations of basic human rights, and to evaluate cases
where these seem to clash with property rights.
- Kyle Fruh
& Marcus Hedahl (forthcoming). Coping with Climate
Change: What Justice Demands of Surfers, Mormons, and the Rest of Us. Ethics, Policy and
Environment.
- Daniel Steel
(forthcoming). Precaution
and Proportionality: A Reply to Turner. Ethics, Policy and
Environment.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
From the end of the twelfth century until the middle of the
eighteenth century, the concept of a right of necessity –i.e. the moral
prerogative of an agent, given certain conditions, to use or take someone
else’s property in order to get out of his plight– was common among moral and
political philosophers, who took it to be a valid exception to the standard
moral and legal rules. In this essay, I analyze Samuel Pufendorf’s account of
such a right, founded on the basic instinct of self-preservation and on the
notion that, in civil society, we have certain minimal duties of humanity
towards each other. I review Pufendorf’s secularized account of natural law,
his conception of the civil state, and the function of private property. I then
turn to his criticism of Grotius’s understanding of the right of necessity as a
retreat to the pre-civil right of common use, and defend his account against
some recent criticisms. Finally, I examine the conditions deemed necessary and
jointly sufficient for this right to be claimable, and conclude by pointing to
the main strengths of this account. Keywords: Samuel Pufendorf, Hugo Grotius,
right of necessity, duty of humanity, private property.
Oct 24th 2013 GMT
- Robert Huseby
(forthcoming). Should
the Beneficiaries Pay? Politics, Philosophy and
Economics:1470594-13506366.
Many theorists claim that if an agent benefits from an action
that harms others, that agent has a moral duty to compensate those who are
harmed, even if the agent did not cause the harm herself. In the debate on
climate justice, this idea is commonly referred to as the beneficiary-pays
principle (BPP). This paper argues that the BPP is implausible, both in the
context of climate change and as a normative principle more generally. It
should therefore be rejected.
- Pradeep P.
Gokhale (2013). An Exclusive Volume on
Exclusion. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):605-616.
Apoha theory could perhaps be understood as a part of the
Buddhist program of emancipating people from the clutches of attachment. Diṅnāga and thereafter
Dharmakīrti, when they developed their epistemology of perception, inference,
and language, pointed out that through perception we are associated with unique
particulars, which are momentary. We try to give an enduring status to them
through thought and language by constructing universals. Thus, thought and
language amount to false constructions, and they also mark our attachment to
the world. Hence, the realization that helps in preventing such an attachment
would imply that inference and language do not really ‘refer to’ or ‘associate
themselves with’ what is ..
- C. K. Raju
(2013). The
Harmony Principle. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):586-604.
I once wrote to Daya ji about what seemed to me a paradox in
contemporary Indian philosophy. It is one thing that Indian philosophers in
academia do not engage with science, or even with its history and philosophy.
It is quite another thing that they do not engage with ethics. Ethics, after
all, is at the core of philosophy. Without an ethical principle one often does
not know how to respond to something fundamentally new, such as the bewildering
variety of new developments in science and technology that impinge on our daily
life. I was disappointed that Indian philosophers remain engaged in the study
of Spinoza, Kant, Hegel, and the like, or are immersed in Sanskrit
texts—neither of which provide much guidance ..
- Daniel Raveh
(2013). Philosophical
Miscellanea: Excerpts From an Ongoing Dialogue with Daya Krishna. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):491-512.
Conversation, dialogue, debate, and discussion are everywhere,
not just in knowledge but in all that man does or seeks, as in these man finds
and feels and discovers what being human is.Questions give birth only to other
questions.I would like to open with short pieces from two letters written by
Daya Krishna (henceforth DK) to his friend, writer-poet-thinker Rameshchandra
Shah,3 sometime in 2006. They reveal the entwinement of the personal and the
philosophical in DK’s thought and illuminate his modes of thinking at the time.
They also work as an overture to my dialogue with DK in the essay that
follows.Dear R. C. Shah,Ancestral Voices4 reached me a few days ago just as I,
along with many others, was trying to ..
- Prabal Kumar Sen
(2013). Daya
Krishna on Some Indian Theories of Negation: A Critique. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):543-561.
Contrary Thinking, an anthology of selected essays by Daya
Krishna, contains, among others, two essays that deal with problems pertaining
to negation: “Negation: Can Philosophy Ever Recover from It?” and “Some
Problems Regarding Thinking about Abhāva in the Indian Tradition.” These essays
comprise part 5 of this book, and the editorial introduction to this part
concludes with the following remark:With characteristic philosophical irony,
Daya Krishna raises the problem that non-being itself is non-existent and that
negation is nothing at all.In both these essays, we find some observations by
Daya Krishna regarding the views about negation (abhāva) that are admitted by
the Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika
schools, and the way in ..
- Michael McGhee
(2013). Learning
to Converse: Reflections on a Small Experiment. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):530-542.
The three of us sweated in the heat and swayed with the rhythms
of the crowded suburban train as we talked—or rather shouted to make ourselves
heard—hanging by straps in the crush as we trundled back toward Andheri West.
We were two Indians, Probal Dasgupta and Prabodh Parikh, and one Britisher,
myself—all around the same age, in our late thirties. It was 1985, and Probal
and I had traveled down from Pune on the Deccan Express to meet Prabodh in
Bombay—and it was also a chance for me to meet the incomparable M. P. Rege. The
polymath and inexhaustible Probal had been a kind (but challenging) friend, and
had gently but firmly introduced me—opened my eyes—to the real-life of India,
including the nature, diversity ..
- Sibesh
Bhattacharya (2013). The Descent of the
Transcendent: Viewing Culture with G. C. Pande. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):513-529.
Govind Chandra Pande’s interest ranged over a wide area. His
early works were on Buddhism, and the very first of his publications
established a secure reputation for him as a leading scholar of Buddhism.1
Other works on Buddhism and other śramaṇa traditions followed to reinforce his
reputation.2 It is therefore not surprising that, to many, this still remains
his primary identity. By training and profession he was a historian. And he
encouraged some of his early research scholars to undertake research in one
area that turned out in many respects to be breaking new ground. The area we
are referring to is the socioeconomic history of early India.3 It has now
become a very coveted field. During the early phase of his ..
- Anand Jayprakash
Vaidya (2013). Nyāya Perceptual
Theory: Disjunctivism or Anti-Individualism? Philosophy East and West 63
(4):562-585.
Misperception is part of the human condition. Consider a classic
case of coming to confirm that one has had a misperception. On a stroll through
the woods you see, in the distance, what seems to be a person. As you draw
near, what looked like a person now appears to be a wooden post with a hat on
it. On arrival you touch the post to confirm that it is not a person. From a
pre-theoretical perspective, what has happened? On your approach you judged
that there was a person, based on what you saw. When near, you judged that it
was a post and not a person, and then by touch you confirmed that what you
initially saw was a misperception.In examining cases of misperception it is
important to ask: what role does concept ..
- Ramesh K.
Sharma (2013). Is Nyāya Realist or
Idealist? Carrying on a Conversation Started by Daya Krishna. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):465-490.
Scholarly disquisitions on Nyāya(-Vaiśeṣika) philosophy in the
English language generally agree in calling it “metaphysical realism” or simply
“realism.” Metaphysical realism or realism as understood in the West is the
doctrine that (1) substances (particulars)/things and events exist
independently of the knowing/thinking mind, and that (2) they exemplify
properties/qualities and enter into relations—in short,
universals—independently of the concepts by which we know them and, Nyāya would
add, even of the language with which we describe them. This mind-independent
world is supposed to be something correspondence with which renders our
particular beliefs/cognitions determinately true or false. Thus, realism, in
all ..
- Jay Garfield
& Arindam Chakrabarti (2013). Remembering Daya
Krishna and G. C. Pande: Two Giants of Post-Independence Indian
Philosophy. Philosophy East and West 63
(4):458-464.
Daya Krishna(Photo courtesy of Jay Garfield)Govind Chandra
Pande(Photo courtesy of his daughter amita sharma)Daya Krishna was the public
face of Indian philosophy in the first half-century after Indian independence.
Nobody on the Indian scene in that period came close to him in influence or in
contribution to the profession. Nobody else in the world thought as hard or as
fruitfully about the relation of Indian philosophy to that of the rest of the
world, and nobody else dared to think as creatively and even as heretically
about the history of Indian philosophy itself. To be sure, the Indian
philosophical scene during this period was always a vibrant and creative matrix
of thought, and many contributed to that ..
- Christopher
Pincock (2013). Review of B. Linsky, The
Evolution of Principia Mathematica: Bertrand Russell's Manuscripts and
Notes for the Second Edition. The Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic 9 (1):106-108.
Review by: Christopher Pincock The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic,
Volume 19, Issue 1, Page 106-108, March 2013.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
In trying to distinguish the right kinds of reasons from the
wrong, epistemologists often appeal to the connection to truth to explain why
practical considerations cannot constitute reasons. The view they typically opt
for is one on which only evidence can constitute a reason to believe. Talbot
has shown that these approaches don’t exclude the possibility that there are
non-evidential reasons for belief that can justify a belief without being
evidence for that belief. He thinksthat there are indeed such reasons and that
they are theright kind of reasons to justify belief. The existence of such
truth promoting non-epistemic reasons is said tofollow from the fact that we
have an epistemic end that involves the attainment of true belief. I shall
argue thatthere are no such reasons precisely because there is anepistemic end
that has normative authority.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Fiora Salis (ed.) (forthcoming). Book Symposium on François
Recanati's Mental Files. Disputatio 5 (36).
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
I examine the meaning and merits of a premise in the Exclusion
Argument, the causal closure principle that all physical effects have physical
causes. I do so by addressing two questions. First, if we grant the other premises,
exactly what kind of closure principle is required to make the Exclusion
Argument valid? Second, what are the merits of the requisite closure principle?
Concerning the first, I argue that the Exclusion Argument requires a strong,
“stringently pure” version of closure. The latter employs two qualifications
concerning the physical sufficiency and relative proximity of the physical
cause required for every physical effect. The second question is addressed in
two steps. I begin by challenging the adequacy of the empirical support offered
by David Papineau for closure. Then I assess the merits of “level” and “domain”
versions of stringently pure closure. I argue that a domain version lacks
adequate and non-question-begging support within the context of the Exclusion
Argument. And I argue that the level version leads to a puzzling metaphysics of
the physical domain. Thus, we have grounds for rejecting the version of closure
required for the Exclusion Argument. This means we can resist the Exclusion
Argument while avoiding the implausible implications that come with rejecting
one of its other premises. That is, because there are grounds to reject causal
closure, one can reasonably affirm the non-overdeterminative causal efficacy of
conscious mental states while denying that the latter are identical with
physical states.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Oct 23rd 2013 GMT
- Bob Hale
(2013). Review
of G. Duke: Dummett on Abstract Objects. Journal for the History
of Analytical Philosophy 2 (2).
Review of G. Duke: Dummett onObjects References G. Frege. Über
Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100,
25–50, 1892. Translated in G.Frege, Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic and
Philosophy, edited by B. McGuinness. Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 157–77. G. Frege.
Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Breslau, Verlag von W. Koebner, 1884. Translated
by J.L. Austin as The Foundations of Arithmetic, Oxford, Basil Blackwell,
second revised edition 1953. M. Dummett. Frege: Philosophy of Language. London,
Duckworth, 1973. M. Dummett. Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics. London:
Duckworth, 1991. B. Hale. Abstract Objects. Oxford: Basil Blackwells, 1987. B.
Hale. Dummett's critique of Wright's attempt to resuscitate Frege. Philosophia
Mathematica 2 (2):122–47 , 1994 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/philmat/2.2.122
B. Hale and C. Wright. The Reason's Proper Study: Essays towards a Neo-Fregean
Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2001. B. Hale and
C. Wright. The Metaontology of Abstraction. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley & R.
Wasserman, editors, Metametaphysics: New essays on the Foundations of Ontology.
Oxford, Clarendon Press, 178–213, 2009. C. Wright. Frege’s Conception of
Numbers as Objects. Scots Philosophical Monographs. Aberdeen, Aberdeen
University Press, 1983.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Matthew R. Dasti (forthcoming). Divine Self, Human Self by
Chakravarthi Ram-Prasad (Bloomsbury 2013). Notre Dame Philosophical
Reviews.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Objective chance and morality are rarely discussed together. In
this paper, I argue that there is a surprising similarity in the epistemic
standing of our beliefs about both objective chance and objective morality. The
key similarity is that both of these sorts of belief are undermined -- in a
limited, but important way -- by plausible genealogical accounts of the
concepts that feature in these beliefs. The paper presents a brief account of
Richard Joyce's evolutionary hypothesis of the genealogy of morality, and
refines the debunking argument which he consequently mounts against moral
beliefs. The evolutionary hypothesis in question suggests that we could easily
have failed to believe that moral judgments have a peculiarly categorical
force. This aspect of our moral belief, then, is unreliable. The paper then
turns to chance, and presents a more speculative hypothesis about the cultural
evolution of ideas about chance, as a peculiarly physical and objective form of
probability. It is argued that, in the same way that our beliefs about morality
could easily have lacked the commitment to inescapable force, our beliefs about
chance could easily have lacked various idiosyncratic commitments. By a similar
argument then, these aspects of our chance beliefs are unreliable. In the final
section of the paper, I review some recent objections to genealogical debunking
arguments, due to Roger White and Guy Kahane, showing how the form of argument
developed in this paper is immune to these criticisms.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Amie Thomasson (2012). Research Problems and
Methods in Metaphysics. In Robert Barnard & Neil
Manson (eds.), The
Continuum Companion to Metaphysics. Continuum International.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Gregor Schiemann (2012). Mehr Seinsschichten für Die
Welt? Vergleich Und Kritik der Schichtenkonzeptionen von Nicolai Hartmann Und
Werner Heisenberg. In G. Hertung & M.
Wunsch (eds.), Nicolai
Hartmann – Von der Systemphilosophie zur Systemetischen Philosophi.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
This journal has frequently taken the position that /consent/,
or at least /informed consent/, is all that from a secular viewpoint is
necessary for an activity to be ethical. We argue to the contrary, that
/consent/ is and /only/ is a /political/ criterion for determining
/criminality/—even for a libertarian. Consensual behavior can be
/unethical/—although it should not be criminalized—if the consent will never be
truly revocable in the future of if such revocability is severely compromised.
We give three examples, one from common experience, and two from the areas
normally covered in this journal.
Note:
I was asked my the senior chief editor to limit categories to five, and have
never exceeded (below) six; proper fine-grained categorization of this piece
would exceed ten categories, so I have done my best with five.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
In this paper, we offer an alternative interpretation for the
claim that ‘S is justified in believing that φ’. First, we present what seems
to be a common way of interpreting this claim: as an attribution of
propositional justification. According to this interpretation, being justified
is just a matter of having confirming evidence. We present a type of case that
does not fit well with the standard concept, where considerations about
cognition are made relevant. The concept of cognitive algorithm is presented
and explained. Finally, the new reading of ‘S is justified in believing that φ’
is fleshed out. According to this interpretation, being justified in believing
that φ is not just a matter of having evidence in favor of φ, but also of
having a cognitive algorithm available such that it allows one to form belief
in φ on the basis of the relevant evidence.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Gregor Schiemann (forthcoming). Lebensweltliche Und
Physikalische Zeit. In G. Hartung (ed.), Mensch und Zeit – Zur Frage
der Synchronisation von Zeitstrukturen. Velbrück.
- Terrence Twomey
(forthcoming). How
Domesticating Fire Facilitated the Evolution of Human Cooperation. Biology and Philosophy:1-11.
Controlled fire use by early humans could have facilitated the
evolution of human cooperation. Individuals with regular access to the benefits
of domestic fire would have been at an advantage over those with limited or no
access. However, a campfire would have been relatively costly for an individual
to maintain and open to free riders. By cooperating, individuals could have
reduced maintenance costs, minimized free riding and lessened the risk of being
without fire. Cooperators were more likely to survive and reproduce than
uncooperative individuals because the former would have been better able to
maximize a fire’s returns and enjoy regular access to its benefits. This is how
the emergence of controlled fire use in Pleistocene human populations could
have facilitated the evolution of cooperation.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Miriam
Kyselo (2013). Enaktivismus. In A.
Stephan & S. Walter (eds.), Handbuch Kognitionswissenschaft. J.B.
Metzler.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Iulian D. Toader (forthcoming). Why Did Weyl Think That
Formalism's Victory Against Intuitionism Entails a Defeat of Pure
Phenomenology? History and Philosophy of Logic.
It has been contended that it is unjustified to believe, as Weyl
did, that formalism's victory against intuitionism entails a defeat of the
phenomenological approach to mathematics. The reason for this contention,
recently put forth by Paolo Mancosu and Thomas Ryckman, is that, unlike
intuitionistic Anschauung, phenomenological intuition could ground classical
mathematics. I argue that this indicates a misinterpretation of Weyl's view,
for he did not take formalism to prevail over intuitionism with respect to
grounding classical mathematics. I also point out that the contention is false:
if intuitionism fails, in the way Weyl thought it did, i.e., with respect to
supporting scientific objectivity, then one should also reject the
phenomenological approach, in the same respect.
Oct 22nd 2013 GMT
- Lauren Wilcox
(2013). The
Image Before the Weapon: A Critical History of the Distinction Between
Civilian and Combatant. Contemporary Political
Theory 12 (4):e14.
- Turkuler Isiksel
(2013). Representing
Justice: Invention, Controversy and Rights in City-States and Democratic
Courtrooms. Contemporary Political
Theory 12 (4):e10.
- Lawrie Balfour
(2013). In
Search of the Black Fantastic: Politics and Popular Culture in the
Post-Civil Rights Era. Contemporary Political
Theory 12 (4):e1.
- Alexander
Livingston (2013). Stuttering Conviction:
Commitment and Hesitation in William James|[Rsquo]| Oration to Robert
Gould Shaw. Contemporary Political
Theory 12 (4):255.
- Gulshan Khan
(2013). Critical
Republicanism: J|[Uuml]|Rgen Habermas and Chantal Mouffe. Contemporary Political
Theory 12 (4):318.
- Claudia Landwehr
(2013). Procedural
Justice and Democratic Institutional Design in Health-Care
Priority-Setting. Contemporary Political
Theory 12 (4):296.
- Nick Malpas
(2013). Responsibility
for Justice. Contemporary Political
Theory 12 (4):e5.
- Banu Bargu
(2013). Human
Shields. Contemporary Political Theory 12
(4):277.
- Kurtis G. Hagen
(forthcoming). Bai,
Tongdong, China: The Political Philosophy of the Middle Kingdom. Dao: A Journal of
Comparative Philosophy:1-5.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Uwe Steinhoff (forthcoming). Helen Frowe’s “Practical
Account of Self-Defence”: A Critique. Public Reason.
Helen Frowe has recently offered what she calls a “practical”
account of self-defense. Her account is supposed to be practical by being
subjectivist about permissibility and objectivist about liability. I shall
argue here that Frowe first makes up a problem that does not exist and then
fails to solve it. To wit, her claim that objectivist accounts of
permissibility cannot be action-guiding is wrong; and her own account of
permissibility actually retains an objectivist (in the relevant sense) element.
In addition, her attempt to restrict subjectivism primarily to “urgent”
situations like self-defense contradicts her own point of departure and is
either incoherent or futile. Finally, the only actual whole-heartedly
objectivist account she criticizes is an easy target; while those objectivist
accounts one finds in certain Western European jurisdictions are immune to her
criticisms. Those accounts are also clearly superior to hers in terms of
action-guidingness.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Barbara Gail Montero (2013). Must Physicalism Imply the
Supervenience of the Mental on the Physical? Journal of Philosophy 110
(2):93-110.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Akiko Frischhut & Alexander Skiles
(forthcoming). Time,
Modality, and the Unbearable Lightness of Being. Thought.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Imagine that in entering a café, you are struck by the absence
of Pierre, with whom you have an appointment. Or imagine that you realize that
your keys are missing because they are not hanging from the usual ring-holder.
What is the nature of these absence experiences? In this paper we discuss a
recent view defended by Farennikova (2012) according to which we literally
perceive absences of things in much the same way as we perceive present things.
We criticize and reject the perceptual interpretation of absence experiences
but we also reject the cognitive view which reduces them to beliefs. We propose
an intermediary, metacognitive account according to which absence experiences
belong to a specific kind of affective experience, involving the feeling of
surprise.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Thaddeus
Metz & Johannes Hirata (2013). Good Governance. In Ilona
Boniwell & Dasho Karma Ura (eds.), Report on Wellbeing &
Happiness. Centre for Bhutan Studies.
A critical discussion of the concept of good governance as it
figures into Bhutan's Gross National Happiness project as part of a report to
the UN General Assembly.
Oct 21st 2013 GMT
- Somogy Varga
(2013). The
Marketization of Foreign Cultural Policy: The Cultural Nationalism of the
Competition State. Constellations 20
(3):442-458.
- Andrew Arato
(2013). Framed.
America's 51 Constitutions and the Crisis of Governance. By Sanford
Levinson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. Constellations 20
(3):503-507.
- Raphaële Chappe,
Willi Semmler & Ed Nell
(2013). The
U.S. Financial Culture of Risk. Constellations 20
(3):422-441.
- Joerg Chet
Tremmel (2013). The Convention of
Representatives of All Generations Under the 'Veil of Ignorance'. Constellations 20
(3):483-502.
- Cristiana
Giordano (2013). Ticktin, Miriam,
Casualties of Care. Immigration and Politics of Humanitarianism in France,
Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011. Constellations 20
(3):510-512.
- Jiří Přibáň
(2013). The
Self‐Referential Semantics of Sovereignty: A
Systems Theoretical Response to (Post)Sovereignty Studies. Constellations 20
(3):406-421.
- Jonathan Trejo‐Mathys (2013). Towards a Critical
Theory of the World Trade Organization: Thinking with Rawls Beyond Rawls. Constellations 20
(3):459-482.
- Jeffrey A.
Bernstein (2013). The Weimar Moment:
Liberalism, Political Theology, and Law. Edited by Leonard V. Kaplan and
Rudy Koshar. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2012. Constellations 20
(3):508-509.
- Craig Borowiak
(2013). Disorienting
Cosmopolitanism: Democratic Accountability and the Politics of Disruption. Constellations 20
(3):372-387.
- Thomas
Biebricher (2013). Critical Theories of
the State: Governmentality and the Strategic‐Relational
Approach. Constellations 20 (3):388-405.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Casey Rentmeester (2013). Perspectivism Narrow and
Wide: An Examination of Nietzsche's Limited Perspectivism From a Daoist Lens. Kritike 7
(1):1-21.
Western liberal intellectuals often find themselves in a
precarious situation with regard to whether or not they should celebrate and
endorse Friedrich Nietzsche as a philosopher who we should all unequivocally
embrace into our Western philosophical canon. While his critique of the Western
philosophical tradition and his own creative insights are unprecedented and
immensely important, his blatant inegalitarianism and remarks against women are
often too difficult to stomach. This paper attempts to introduce Western
philosophers to Chuang Tzu, a Chinese thinker who shares much of Nietzsche’s
style and philosophy, but also espouses a thoroughgoing egalitarianism. It does
so by comparing Nietzsche and Chuang Tzu in regard to their methods, style, and
philosophical beliefs, with a particular emphasis on the naturalism and
perspectivism found in each thinker’s philosophy. The hope is to provide
Western liberal-minded intellectuals interested in Nietzsche and in equality
with another perspective to bolster their thinking.
- Rachael L.
Brown (2013). Learning,
Evolvability and Exploratory Behaviour: Extending the Evolutionary Reach
of Learning. Biology and Philosophy 28
(6):933-955.
Traditional accounts of the role of learning in evolution have
concentrated upon its capacity as a source of fitness to individuals. In this
paper I use a case study from invasive species biology—the role of conditioned
taste aversion in mitigating the impact of cane toads on the native species of
Northern Australia—to highlight a role for learning beyond this—as a source of
evolvability to populations. This has two benefits. First, it highlights an
otherwise under-appreciated role for learning in evolution that does not rely
on social learning as an inheritance channel nor “special” evolutionary
processes such as genetic accommodation (both of which many are skeptical
about). Second, and more significantly, it makes clear important and
interesting parallels between learning and exploratory behaviour in
development. These parallels motivate the applicability of results from existing
research into learning and learning evolution to our understanding of the
evolution of evolvability more generally.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
María G. Navarro (forthcoming). El Razonamiento Ordinario y
Sus Heurísticas. In Magda Bandera (ed.), La Uni en la calle. Libro de
textos. La marea ediciones.
Las heurísticas son procedimientos de estimación utilizados por
todos nosotros al razonar en nuestra vida ordinaria.
- Thomas
Christiano (2013). Introduction to
Symposium on Exploitation. Politics, Philosophy and
Economics 12 (4):333-334.
- Vida Panitch
(forthcoming). Global
Surrogacy: Exploitation to Empowerment. Journal of Global Ethics.
(2013). Economic Exploitation in Intercollegiate Athletics.
Sport, Ethics and Philosophy: Vol. 7, No. 3, pp. 295-312. doi:
10.1080/17511321.2013.824499.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
(2013). The modal view of essence. Canadian Journal of
Philosophy: Vol. 43, No. 2, pp. 248-266.
- Jesse M. Mulder
(forthcoming). The
Essentialist Inference. Australasian Journal of
Philosophy.
Oct 19th 2013 GMT
- Ariel Caticha
(forthcoming). Towards
an Informational Pragmatic Realism. Minds and Machines:1-34.
I discuss the design of the method of entropic inference as a
general framework for reasoning under conditions of uncertainty. The main
contribution of this discussion is to emphasize the pragmatic elements in the
derivation. More specifically: (1) Probability theory is designed as the
uniquely natural tool for representing states of incomplete information. (2) An
epistemic notion of information is defined in terms of its relation to the
Bayesian beliefs of ideally rational agents. (3) The method of updating from a
prior to a posterior probability distribution is designed through an
eliminative induction process that singles out the logarithmic relative entropy
as the unique tool for inference. The resulting framework includes as special
cases both MaxEnt and Bayes’ rule. It therefore unifies entropic and Bayesian
methods into a single general inference scheme. I find that similar pragmatic
elements are an integral part of Putnam’s internal realism, of Floridi’s
informational structural realism, and also of van Fraasen’s empiricist
structuralism. I conclude with the conjecture that their valuable insights can
be incorporated into a single coherent doctrine—an informational pragmatic
realism.
- Elizabeth Woo Li
(forthcoming). Chen,
Lai 陳來,
Ancient Religion and Ethics: Sources of Confucian Thought 宗教與倫理:
儒家思想的根源,
Yunchen Wenhua 允辰文化, Taipei 台北, 2005, 375 Pages; and The
World of Ancient Thought and Culture: Religion, Ethics, and Social Thought
in the Spring and Autumn Period 古代思想文化世界—春秋時代的宗教、倫理與社會思想,
Sanlian Shudian 三聯書店, Beijing 北京, 2002, 418 Pages. Dao: A Journal of
Comparative Philosophy:1-5.
- Aaron Stalnaker
(forthcoming). Confucianism,
Democracy, and the Virtue of Deference. Dao: A Journal of
Comparative Philosophy:1-19.
Some democratic theorists have argued that contemporary people
should practice only a civility that recognizes others as equal persons, and
eschew any form of deference to authority as a feudalistic cultural holdover
that ought to be abandoned in the modern era. Against such views, this essay
engages early Confucian views of ethics and society, including their analyses
of different sorts of authority and status, in order to argue that, properly
understood, deference is indeed a virtue of considerable importance for
contemporary democratic societies and the citizens who constitute them.
- Sungmoon Kim
(forthcoming). Confucianism
and Acceptable Inequalities. Philosophy and Social
Criticism:0191453713507015.
In this article, I explore an alternative model of Confucian
distributive justice, namely the ‘family model’, by challenging the central
claim of recent sufficientarian justifications of Confucian justice offered by
Confucian political theorists – roughly, that inequalities of wealth and income
beyond the threshold of sufficiency do not matter if they reflect different
merits. I argue (1) that the telos of Confucian virtue politics – moral
self-cultivation and fiduciary society – puts significant moral and
institutional constraints on inequality even if it meets the threshold of
sufficiency and largely results from differing individual merits; (2) that the
Confucian moral ideal of the family state establishes and gives justification
to the ‘family model’ of distributive justice that shifts the focus from desert
to vulnerability and from causal responsibility to remedial responsibility. The
article concludes by presenting Confucian democracy as the socio-political
institution and practice that can best realize the Confucian intuition of the
family model of justice.
Oct 18th 2013 GMT
- Stephen John
(forthcoming). Efficiency,
Responsibility and Disability: Philosophical Lessons From the Savings
Argument for Pre-Natal Diagnosis. Politics, Philosophy and
Economics:1470594-13505412.
Pre-natal-diagnosis technologies allow parents to discover
whether their child is likely to suffer from serious disability. One argument
for state funding of access to such technologies is that doing so would be
“cost-effective”, in the sense that the expected financial costs of such a
programme would be outweighed by expected “benefits”, stemming from the births
of fewer children with serious disabilities. This argument is extremely
controversial. This paper argues that the argument may not be as unacceptable
as is often assumed. In doing so, it sets out a more general framework for
assessing the relevance of efficiency calculations to policy-making. The final
section also investigates the relationship between the paper’s arguments and
claims about parental responsibility for child-bearing and rearing, with
reference to Scanlon’s work on “substantive responsibility”.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Erin C. Tarver (2013). The Dismissal of Feminist
Philosophy and Hostility to Women in the Profession. APA Newsletter on Feminist
Philosophy 12 (2):8-11.
Species concepts aim to define the species category. Many of
these rely on defining species in terms of natural lineages and groupings. A
dominant gene-centred metaconception has shaped notions of what constitutes
both a natural lineage and a natural grouping. I suggest that relying on this
metaconception provides an incomplete understanding of what constitute natural
lineages and groupings. If we take seriously the role of epigenetic,
behavioural, cultural, and ecological inheritance systems, rather than
exclusively genetic inheritance, a broader notion of what constitutes a natural
grouping or lineage may be required. I conclude by outlining an alternative
metaconception that is a de-centred metaschema for species.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Nicholas Tebben (2013). Peer Disagreement and the
Limits of Coherent Error Attribution. Logos and Episteme 4
(2):179-197.
I argue that, in an important range of cases, judging that one
disagrees with an epistemic peer requires attributing, either to one's peer or
to oneself, a failure of rationality. There are limits, however, to how much
irrationality one can coherently attribute, either to oneself or to another. I
argue that these limitations on the coherent attribution of rational error put
constraints on permissible responses to peer disagreement. In particular, they
provide reason to respond to one-off disagreements with a single peer by
maintaining one's beliefs, and they provide reason to moderate one's beliefs
when faced with repeated disagreement, or disagreement with multiple peers.
Finally, I argue that, though peer disagreement is rare, the occasions on which
it does occur tend to be especially important, and the kind of response
supported here is correspondingly important. In particular, how leading
researchers spend their time and effort depends, in part, on how they respond
to peer disagreement. And only a response of the kind supported here strikes
the right balance between allowing individual researchers to freely pursue what
seems to them to be worthwhile projects, and requiring that they pursue those
research projects that the community of experts as a whole believes to be
likely to yield significant results.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Tim Connolly (forthcoming). Sagehood and
Supererogation in the Analects. Journal of Chinese Philosophy.
- Aj Julius
(2013). The
Possibility of Exchange. Politics, Philosophy and
Economics 12 (4):361-374.
I first characterize a moral mistake in coercion. The principle
of independence with which I criticize coercion seems also to condemn exchange.
I propose an account of exchange from which it follows that exchange upholds
independence after all. In support of that account I argue that, of the
accounts of exchange that occur to me, only this one has the consequence that,
on general assumptions, a person can take part in exchange while acting, intending,
and believing with sufficient reason. I argue that the hiring of very poor
people by very rich people for labor from which the rich draw a substantial
surplus does not give rise to an exchange of this kind. These instances of the
wage labor relation resemble coercion insofar as they violate independence.
- Hui-Chieh Loy
(forthcoming). On
the Argument for Jian'ai. Dao: A Journal of
Comparative Philosophy:1-18.
In all three versions of the “Jian’ai” 兼愛 Chapter in the Mozi 墨子, variations of a central argument may be
found. This argument proceeds by advancing a diagnosis for what causes the
various evils that beset the world, and it is on this basis that the Mohists
propose jian’ai as the solution. The study examines this main argument in some
detail, with the aim of improving both our understanding of the Mohist ethical
doctrine and also our appreciation of their argumentative practices. The study
shows that distinct ethical injunctions of varying degrees of stringency can be
derived from the argument, though they all embody an underlying notion of
impartiality. This impartiality—while in many ways recognizably attractive to
us—puts Mohist jian’ai in tension with certain notions regarding the ethical
significance of special relations. In addition, the paper argues that the
Mohists main argument for jian’ai contains a critical flaw.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Errol Lord (forthcoming). Epistemic Reasons,
Evidence, and Defeaters. In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of
Reasons and Normativity. Oxford University Press.
The post-Gettier literature contained many views that tried to
solve the Gettier problem by appealing to the notion of defeat. Unfortunately,
all of these views are false. The failure of these views greatly contributed to
a general distrust of reasons in epistemology. However, reasons are making a
comeback in epistemology, both in general and in the context of the Gettier
problem. There are two main aims of this paper. First, I will argue against a
natural defeat based resolution of the Gettier problem. Second, I will defend
my own defeat based solution. This solution appeals to a modal anti-luck
condition. I will argue that this condition captures anti-luck intuitions and
has virtues that rival modal anti-luck conditions lack.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Hannes Rusch (2013). Asymmetries in Altruistic
Behavior During Violent Intergroup Conflict. Evolutionary Psychology 11
(5):973-993.
Recent theoretical and experimental investigations of altruistic
behavior in intergroup conflict in humans frequently make use of the assumption
that warfare can be modeled as a symmetrical n-person prisoner’s dilemma,
abstracting away the strategic differences between attack and defense. In
contrast, some empirical studies on intergroup conflict in hunter-gatherer
societies and chimpanzees indicate that fitness relevant risks and potential
benefits of attacks and defenses might have differed substantially under ancestral
conditions. Drawing on these studies, it is hypothesized that the success of
defenses was much more important for individual and kin survival and that a
disposition to act altruistically during intergroup conflict is thus more
likely to evolve for the strategic situation of defense. It is then
investigated empirically if such asymmetries in the occurrence of altruistic
behavior during intergroup conflict can be found. Analyzing detailed historical
case data from 20th century wars, this study finds that altruistic behavior
towards members of the in-group indeed seems to occur more frequently when
soldiers are defending themselves and their comrades against enemy attacks. It
is proposed that this asymmetry reflects adaptive behavioral responses to the
materially different strategic character of attacks and defenses under
ancestral conditions. If true, this would call for a refinement of theories of
the evolutionary interaction of intergroup conflict and altruism.
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
Rasmus Grønfeldt Winther & Fabrizzio
Guerrero McManus (forthcoming). Review of Michael Ruse, The
Philosophy of Human Evolution. 2012. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.
ISBN: 978052113372. $26.99 Paperback. Evolution.
Oct 17th 2013 GMT
- DIRECT SUBMISSION
According to a common view, prejudice always involves some form
of epistemic culpability, i.e., a failure to respond to evidence in the
appropriate way. I argue that the common view wrongfully assumes that
prejudices always involve universal generalizations. After motivating the more
plausible thesis that prejudices typically involve a species of generic
judgment, I show that standard examples provide no grounds for positing a
strong connection between prejudice and epistemic culpability. More generally,
the common view fails to recognize the extent to which prejudices are
epistemically insidious: once they are internalized as background beliefs, they
quite reasonably come to control the assessment and interpretation of new
evidence. This property of insidiousness helps explain why prejudices are so
recalcitrant to empirical counterevidence and also why they are frequently
invisible to introspective reflection.
- Alexander Brown
(forthcoming). What
Should Egalitarians Believe If They Really Are Egalitarian? A Reply to
Martin O'Neill. European Journal of
Political Theory:1474885113506710.
In his article, ‘What Should Egalitarians Believe?’, Martin
O’Neill argues, amongst other things, that egalitarians should reject both
Telic and Deontic Egalitarianism and that they should adopt in their place a
version of Non-Intrinsic Egalitarianism, specifically, the Pluralist Non-Intrinsic
Egalitarian View. The central purpose of my article is to challenge O’Neill’s
assumption that he can defend each of the various propositions that make up his
position simultaneously. I do this with two arguments. First, I argue that in
order to justify why egalitarians should adopt a version of Non-Intrinsic
Egalitarianism, O’Neill is bound to rely on forms of egalitarianism that are
either Telic or Deontic, and so he is no longer able to affirm that
egalitarians should reject both Telic and Deontic Egalitarianism. Second, I
argue that by allowing the inclusion of non-egalitarian reasons into the
Pluralist Non-Intrinsic Egalitarian View, O’Neill opens the floodgates to an
indefinite number of other non-egalitarian reasons, such that it is scarcely
credible that the Pluralist Non-Intrinsic Egalitarian View really is an
egalitarian view after all.
Δεν υπάρχουν σχόλια:
Δημοσίευση σχολίου